[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Re: [xmca] Spanning Traditions: ingold and vygotsky



Thanks for that, Tony. And anyone else who has some gems from anywhere on concepts that I may have overlooked, send them my way.
As I see it, in this excert, Adorno sets off from an idealist 
understanding of "concepts" himself, so as to prove that philosophy is 
doomed to idealism by making concepts its subject matter. I think you 
have to be a Vygotskyist or Activity Theorist of some kind that 
understands the essential place of mediation in communication, to read 
Hegel other than as an idealist. It's to do with that sedimentation of 
culture we all just spoke about. Since Adorno's generation of Critical 
Theorists, knew only Freud and the "social psychology" of the crowd, 
this was ruled out. (My mind is still open about Merleau-Ponty but it 
appears that otherwise the situation has not improved in Critical Theory).
Andy

Tony Whitson wrote:
On Sun, 25 Sep 2011, Andy Blunden wrote:

Currently, I am writing a book on Concepts, which is meant to make inroads into analytical science.
Might Adorno be of interest? Here's from Adorno, Theodor W. Negative 
Dialectics. New York: Seabury Press (1973) Continuum (1983):
[p. 11] DISENCHANTMENT OF THE CONCEPT

Philosophy, Hegel's included, invites the general objection that by inevitably having concepts for its material it anticipates an idealistic decision. In fact no philosophy, not even extreme empiricism, can drag in the _facta bruta_ and present them like cases in anatomy or experiments in physics; no philosophy can paste the particulars into the text, as seductive paintings would hoodwink it into believing. But the argument in its formality and generality takes as fetishistic a view of the concept as the concept does in interpreting itself naïvely in its own domain: in either case it is regarded as a self-sufficient totality over which philosophical thought has no power. In truth, all concepts, even the philosophical ones, refer to nonconceptualities, because concepts on their part are moments of the reality that requires their formation, primarily for the control of nature. What conceptualization appears to be from within, to one engaged in it--the predominance of its sphere, without which nothing is known--must not be mistaken for what it is in itself. Such a semblance of being-in-itself is conferred upon it by the motion that exempts it from reality, to which it is har¬nessed in turn.
Necessity compels philosophy to operate with concepts, but this 
necessity must not be turned into the virtue of their priority--no 
more than, conversely, criticism of that virtue can be turned into a 
summary verdict against philosophy. On the other hand, the insight 
that philosophy's conceptual knowledge is not the absolute
[p. 12] of philosophy--this insight, for all its inescapability, is 
again due to the nature of the concept. It is not a dogmatic thesis, 
much less a naïvely realistic one. Initially, such concepts as that of 
"being" at the start of Hegel's _Logic_ emphatically mean 
nonconceptualities; as Lask put it, they "mean beyond themselves." 
Dissatisfaction with their own conceptuality is part of their meaning, 
although the inclusion of nonconceptuality in their meaning makes it 
tendentially their equal and thus keeps them trapped within 
themselves. The substance of concepts is to them both immanent, as far 
as the mind is concerned, and transcendent as far as being is 
concerned. To be aware of this is to be able to get rid of concept 
fetishism. Philosophical reflection makes sure of the nonconceptual in 
the concept. It would be empty otherwise, according to Kant's dictum; 
in the end, having ceased to be a concept of anything at all, it would 
be nothing.
A philosophy that lets us know this, that extinguishes the autarky of 
the concept, strips the blindfold from our eyes. That the concept is a 
concept even when dealing with things in being does not change the 
fact that on its part it is entwined with a non-conceptual whole. Its 
only insulation from that whole is its reification--that which 
establishes it as a concept. The concept is an element in dialectical 
logic, like any other. What survives in it is the fact that 
nonconceptuality has conveyed it by way of its meaning, which in turn 
establishes its conceptuality. To refer to nonconceptualities--as 
ultimately, according to traditional epistemology, every definition of 
concepts requires nonconceptual, deictic elements--is characteristic 
of the concept, and so is the contrary: that as the abstract unit of 
the noumena subsumed thereunder it will depart from the noumenal. To 
change this direction of conceptuality, to give it a turn toward 
nonidentity, is the hinge of negative dialectics. Insight into the 
constitutive character of the nonconceptual in the concept would end 
the compulsive identification which the concept brings unless halted 
by such reflection. Reflection upon its own meaning is the way out of 
the concept's seeming being-in-itself as a unit of meaning.
--
------------------------------------------------------------------------
*Andy Blunden*
Joint Editor MCA: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~db=all~content=g932564744
Home Page: http://home.mira.net/~andy/
Book: http://www.brill.nl/default.aspx?partid=227&pid=34857

__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca