11

The Crisis in Psychology
279
p. 7] justly claims that the purpose of any comparison and the task of comparative
science is not only to distinguish similar traits, but even more to search for the
differences within the similarity. Comparative psychology, consequently, must not
merely understand man as an animal, but much more as a non-animal.
The straightforward application of the principle led to a ubiquitous search for
similarity. A correct method and reliably established facts led to monstrously
strained interpretations and distorted facts when applied uncritically. Children’s
games have indeed traditionally preserved many echoes of the remote past (the
play with bows, round dances). For Hall this is the repetition and expression in
innocent form of the animal and pre-historic stages of development. Groos consid-
ers this to show a remarkable lack of critical judgment. The fear of cats and dogs
would be a remnant of the time when these animals were still wild. Water would
attract children because we developed from aquatic animals. The automatic move-
ments of the infant’s arms would be a remnant of the movements of our ancestors
who swam in the water, etc.
The mistake resides, consequentiy, in the interpretation of the child’s whole
behavior as a recapitulation and in the absence of any principle to verify the analogy
and to select the facts which must and must not be interpreted. It is precisely the
play of animals which cannot be explained in this way. “Can Hall’s theory explain
the play of the young tiger with its victim?”—asks Groos [1904/1921, p. 73]. It is
clear that this play cannot be understood as a recapitulation of past phylogenetic
development. It foreshadows the future activity of the tiger and not a repetition of
his past development. It must be explained and understood in relation to the tiger’s
future, in the light of which it gets its meaning, and not in the light of the past of
his species. The past of the species comes out in a totally different sense: through
the individual’s future which it predetermines, but not directly and not in the sense
of a repetition.
What are the facts? This quasi-biological theory appears to be untenable pre-
cisely in biological terms, precisely in comparison with the nearest homogeneous
analogue in the series of homogeneous phenomena in other stages of evolution. When
we compare the play of a child with the play of a tiger, i.e., a higher mammal, and
consider not only the similarity, but the difference as well, we will lay bare their
common biological essence which resides exactly in theft difference (the tiger plays
the chase of tigers; the child that he is a grown-up; both practice necessary functions
for theft life to come—Groos’ theory). But despite all the seeming similarity in the
comparison of heterogeneous phenomena (play with water—aquatic life of the am-
phibian—man) the theory is biologically meaningless.
Thorndike [1906] adds to this devastating argument a remark about the dif-
ferent order of the same biological principles in onto- and phylogencsis. Thus, con-
sciousness appears very early in ontogenesis and very late in phylogenesis. The
sexual drive, on the other hand, appears very early in phylogenesis and very late
in ontogenesis. Stern [1927, pp. 266-267], using similar considerations, criticizes the
same theory in its application to play.
Blonsky (1921) makes another kind of mistake. He defends—and very con-
vincingly—this law for embryonic development from the viewpoint of biomechanics
and shows that it would be miraculous if it did not exist. The author points out
the hypothetical nature of the considerations (“not very conclusive”) leading to this
contention (“it may be like this”), i.e., he gives arguments for the methodological
possibility of a working hypothesis, but then, instead of proceeding to the investi-
gation and verification of the hypothesis, follows in Hall’s footsteps and begins to
explain the child’s behavior on the basis of very intelligible analogies: he does not
view the climbing of trees by children as a recapitulation of the life of apes, but

11