[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Re: [xmca] Tom Toolery



I was curious where you might go with this materiality versus reality distinction, David. I suggest that it might be easier all around to see the two terms as synonymous, rather than counterpose them. I'll try to present my reasoning. I think some of the problem here is probably just semantic - meaning we can get to the same place in more than one way word-wise, which is fine. More important is to try get to the heart of the question, which I'll give a stab at.
As we all know, there are several very tricky and slippery aspects to  
this discussion, which is now probably at least 6,000 years old, or  
maybe even as old as oral language.  Part of what makes CHAT so  
interesting to me is how it takes certain relatively unique and  
exciting approaches to psychology and subjectivity on these kinds of  
issues.
The questions before us could be identified as three:

1) How to differentiate materiality and ideality; while figuring out
2) how to grasp what the two are both simultaneously part of; while also figuring out
3) how to take into account ALL of reality.

I think David is trying to deal with all three of these questions in his discussion of reality and materiality, which I think is heading in just the right direction.
Ilyenkov explained that Descartes solved questions 1) and 2) by  
suggesting that what we are now calling ideality and materiality are  
two disconnected forms of reality.  In Descartes' terms, thought and  
extension do not interact, except through God.  It is through God that  
humans are able to think and act on the world.  But this dualist  
solution is untenable for modern natural science, and has been largely  
abandoned.  We do still see it, often in disguised forms in the modern  
social sciences, in the form of debates over the relationship of the  
subject and object.
Ilyenkov in another essay explained that Kant answered the Cartesians  
and solved question 1) by differentiating what is inside people's  
heads from what is outside.   This is a familiar and popular solution  
today - it is plain, everyday, common sense materialism.  The ideal is  
that which we think in our heads, the material is everything else.  In  
fact, Ilyenkov points out that even everyday idealism agrees on this  
boundary.  But this solution leaves question 2) unsolved.  How do we  
grasp what the ideal and material are both part of?
Hegel came up with a new and brilliant solution to 2).  Materiality  
and ideality, according to Hegel, are simultaneously and integrally  
components of human activity and history.  They **develop**.  By  
posing the concept of development as fundamental, he showed ways of  
differentiating ideality and materiality.  In doing so, he showed ways  
of answering how to **differentiate** ideality and materiality in  
question 1) while also grasping their **unity** in question 2).
But Ilyenkov explains, like all idealists, Hegel could not see or  
explain a reality beyond the ideal, beyond the collectively created  
consciousness (representations, reflections, etc.) of humanity.   
Ilyenkov called this limitation the "secret twist of idealism."    
Unlike Descartes, Kant, Plato, and most of the great idealist  
philosophers before him, Hegel could see ideality and materiality  
**developmentally**.  He could see ideality in a **historical** way.   
But ultimately, like all idealists, at the level of theory he could  
not clearly differentiate materiality from ideality.  He could only  
explain reality in the limited bourgeois, Eurocentric terms of human  
history as he understood it, and human history in the mystical terms  
of the Absolute Idea.  Hegel through his philosophical system could  
not articulate the nature of materiality itself.  Hegel could only see  
the world in terms of standing on the human head.
Marx and Engels, owing many of their insights to Feuerbach, French and  
English materialists, the many accomplishments of bourgeois science,  
and of course, to Hegel, offered an entirely new solution to all three  
questions.  1) Yes, as the materialists argued, materiality and  
ideality are differentiable; 2) and, yes, as Hegel began to discover,  
ideality is an historical product; and also, in a new contribution to  
social theory, 3) ideality is a specialized form of material reality,  
which is the essence of all reality (being), including consciousness.   
They also added to social theory still another new idea, still being  
debated by many Marxists, that 4) nature, like society and thought, is  
itself dialectical and developmental.
Marx and Engels thereby helped transform the traditional problems of  
philosophy into modern problems of science, history and politics.   
They contributed to shifting the objects of philosophy from abstract  
topics discussed by the owning classes to the concrete challenges of  
working people becoming the subjects of history.  They began a  
monumental shift in the axis of human thought from owning to acting,  
from capital to labor.
These, more or less, if you will forgive my injustices to them with my  
homespun terminology, are the methodological and philosophical bases  
upon which the Vygotsky school and the cultural-historical tradition  
were founded, and which help make CHAT unique in the social sciences.
In this viewpoint, ontologically speaking (that is, with regard to the  
nature of existence), the terms reality and materiality are synonyms.   
At the same time, epistemologically speaking (that is, with regard to  
the nature of consciousness) ideality is a complex form  
(representation, reflection, etc.) of materiality, or reality.
In human historical development and cultural activities, ideality and  
materiality are opposites because humans - through the means of labor  
and activity, which are inherently bound with ideality (roughly  
speaking, forms of meaning-making) - are constantly transforming  
reality (materiality).  According to this perspective, in all human  
processes, macro and micro, this opposition between ideality and  
materiality is always in play.
In this outlook, part of the challenge of psychology in general and  
cultural psychology in particular is to discover and explain the very  
complex ways and forms by which ideality figures into each and every  
material action of humans, and the ways materiality figures into each  
and every subjective (ideality-based) process humans engage in.  This  
requires tons of subtle terms and distinctions from all disciplines  
(such as perhaps distinguishing signs versus tools, or household  
utensils versus industrial tools, or signs versus symbols).  Taking  
into account the dialectical relationship of ideality and materiality  
is only a way to get started.
I believe, as I think did Vygotsky, that this is a solid  
methodological and philosophical foundation to get us started which  
can help us explore all the fascinating things we do - including  
opening packs of peanuts with our teeth, or perhaps training pet crows  
to sit next to us on airline seats to do it for us.
- Steve


On Oct 18, 2010, at 8:19 PM, David Kellogg wrote:

Sure, Jenna.

But the way my head works, I think in EXAMPLES. And the first example that springs to mind is almost always a WORD. It drives my poor students crazy.
                WORD VALUE
sense-value           signification-value
("I", "it", "and")        ("elephant", "kick", "time")

You can see that words like "I" and "it" and "he" and "she" and "but" and even "because" depend almost entirely on circumstances for their interpretation. That's not true of words like "elephant" and "kick" which can be put in dictionaries.
We tend to think of languages as being made up of signification- 
values, partly because these are more official. But historically,  
and also in every day life, sense-values are much more frequent and  
are historically the source of signification-values.
Of course, it's true that we make our individual sense-values with  
the help of signification-values. For example, we ask "What time is  
it?" more or less the same way every time we ask, and we can answer  
in the same way exactly twice a day even though the true answer is,  
by definition, never the same. Sociogenetically, sense-value  
produces signification-value, just as microgenetically signification- 
value produces sense value.
We see (more or less) this relationship with use value and exchange  
value, and that is where the distinction between utensil-artefacts  
and tool-artefacts really comes into play.
          ARTEFACTS
utensil-artefacts   tool-artefacts
(chopsticks)        (screwdrivers)

The former is an implement for personal consumption; it's a "sense- artefact". The latter is a tool for production; it's a "meaning- artefact". So the former is really concerned with use, and the latter with production and exchange.
The distinction between signals and symbols is not really mine; it's  
something Vygotsky uses in his struggle with behaviorism (which  
involved, if we read "Psychology of Art", both internal strife and  
external).
When the leaves turn red, that is a signal of winter, and it was  
before humans ever existed. A footprint in the sand is the sign that  
somebody has been walking on the beach, whether you are a speaker of  
English or Korean. Signals are older, and much more common, than  
signs.
When you say the word "red" or when you spell the word "foot", that  
too is a sign. But it is  means absolutely nothing unless you are  
speaking to somebody who knows English. So we say it is a symbol.  
Symbols seem much more "typical" of signs, but they are in reality  
merely more official, more formalized, more systematic and less  
context bound.
And that brings me to reality and ideality. But here I am really  
going to catch it from Andy, because "real" means something quite  
different to him (in Hegel it includes the idea of rationality, of  
what it is that gets "realized" when we realize something).
But I do feel the need for a superordinate category, and since I am  
a materialist, that superordinate category is in the final analysis  
material. That means I need something to counterpose to the ideal,  
the potential, the past and the future. I could call it the "hic"  
and "nunc" but I prefer "real" because...well, because it rhymes  
with "ideal".
David Kellogg (correcting midterms at)
Seoul National University of Education

PS: Larry--I just read your post, and I have to get back to these midterms. But like you, like Martin, I am working on the problems between Piaget and Vygotsky right now (I'm retranslating and commenting on Piaget's riposte to Chapter Two and Chapter Six of T&S).
I think you are ABSOLUTELY right--part of the real difference, the  
real distinction, the break that cannot be denied between Piaget on  
the one hand and Vygotsky on the other is that Piaget believes that  
the sociocultural is really only important in the history of science.
For him, everything else is interpersonal, or as you put it,  
relational. That's the weird, wordless, undialectical way he thinks.  
But the interpersonal is not the sociocultural, any more than the  
words that we get still warm from each other's lungs and lips are  
reducible to the ones we find printed in dictionaries, or the words  
we still read in Vygotsky's books have faded away with the "crumbly,  
yellow voice" that Vygotsky supposedly had (according to one of his  
patients).
dk


--- On Mon, 10/18/10, Jenna McWilliams <jennamcjenna@gmail.com> wrote:


From: Jenna McWilliams <jennamcjenna@gmail.com>
Subject: Re: [xmca] Tom Toolery
To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
Date: Monday, October 18, 2010, 7:30 PM


David, for those of us trying desperately to cling to this thread, can you add some explanation to help with interpreting those categories?



On Oct 18, 2010, at 10:20 PM, David Kellogg wrote:

Nothing, Andy. That's why I want to oppose the ideal to the real, and not to the material.
              ARTEFACT:
Tool-artefact       Utensil-artefact
(mass production)  (personal consumption)

                 SIGN
Signal-sign         Symbol-sign
(thing-thing)        (meaning-meaning)]

         MATERIALITY
Reality               Ideality
(percepts)          (concepts)

David Kellogg
Seoul National University of Education

--- On Mon, 10/18/10, Andy Blunden <ablunden@mira.net> wrote:


From: Andy Blunden <ablunden@mira.net>
Subject: Re: [xmca] Tom Toolery
To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
Date: Monday, October 18, 2010, 7:02 PM


What would be an example of something which is ideal but not also material, David?
andy
David Kellogg wrote: ...
It seems to me that if we follow Steve and Ilyenkov, and we see problem after problem as a matter of establishing the interaction of "ideal" and "material", we will need some kind of super- category for the indivisible whole which both ideal and material make up. Otherwise we really do fall into the worst kind of Cartesian dualism. ...

__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca




__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca
__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca




__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca
__________________________________________
_____
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca