[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Re: [xmca] Types of Generalization: concepts and pseudoconcepts



Andy, thanks for your response to Davydov on concept formation and efforts to get us to read Davydov, Vygotsky, Sakharov, etc. It has certainly been effective in my case. And Jay, your comments have also been very helpful.
Two questions on your essay, Andy.

One, what do you mean by "an absolutely non-empirical social factor" when you say: "The transition from complex to concept is a protracted and complex process, but one which necessarily involves a complex leap, in which absolutely non-empirical, social factors enter into the formation and enrichment of the concept."
Two, I am having difficulty understanding how Sakharov block solutions  
for bik, cev, lag and mur are not "true concepts" in the way Vygotsky  
used the term.  A taxonomy formed out of formal rules can be a true  
concept, yes?  The Sakharov block test is really just a puzzle where  
you have to figure out the taxonomic classification system by  
observing the visible attributes of the blocks and figuring out the  
only one that can be put into four logical groups.  Yes, the nonsense  
words are arbitrary and only have meaning to test participants - but  
that is the case for any game.  In chess, for example, rooks and pawns  
are "concepts" - yes?  If a rook is a concept, then why not bik, cev,  
mur and lag?
******************

Here are some details on the Sakharov test and its solution that might help visualize this question of whether the solution groups to the test are themselves "true concepts". In discussing details to the solution to the test the way I do, I am arguing that the solution groups are "true concepts." I am willing to be corrected on this, of course. Perhaps there is a better way to interpret these details.
The 22 Sakharov blocks were very cleverly designed.  No two blocks are  
exactly alike.  They are comprised of 6 different colors, 5 different  
geometric shapes, 2 different heights (tall and flat) and 2 different  
sizes (large and small).  There would be 120 (6*5*2*2=120) different  
blocks altogether if a full set of blocks were created out of these  
parameters.  The 22 that were selected have the interesting  
characteristic of having one and one only possible rule-based solution  
to the challenge of sorting them into 4 logical groups based on their  
physical attributes.
Since there are 4 groups that these 22 blocks are going to fall in,  
one's first impulse is to look for a single parameter that all blocks  
share that has 4 variations.  As it turns out, this is impossible.   
There is no 4*1=4 solution.  That took some serious design  
forethought.  There are not even any clever, obscure alternative  
solutions along these lines.
In one of Paula's earlier papers, she reports on a child who, after  
deciding that neither color nor shape would work as solutions, began  
counting numbers of **sides** of the blocks to see if **that**  
parameter fell into 4 groups.  It doesn't - they fall into 5 groups.   
That little inspiration got me me to try to come up with some other  
way of grouping the blocks into 4 logical groups by seeking unusual  
parameters, such as numbers of angles, numbers of two-surface  
intersections, numbers of three-surface intersections.  However, no  
single parameter I have come up with has has only 4 variations.  (As  
an aside, most of these parameters just mentioned, interestingly, have  
5 variations - the reason being that all the 6 different geometric  
shapes have different totals of these unusual parameters except the  
square and trapezoid, which have the same number of these - so  
consequently, the total of 5 keeps reappearing).
I don't think it is a coincidence that there are no alternative  
solutions. I am guessing that Sakharov very deliberately designed  
these blocks to avoid that distraction.  This is part of this test's  
very clever design.
What makes this test a puzzle even to most adults is that the solution  
requires not finding one parameter with 4 variations, but combining  
**2** parameters that each have **2** variations.  I think Paula calls  
this a dichotomous solution (Paula, do I have the right word?).   
Running into this principle in the way this test presents it is not an  
everyday occurrence, but the principle is actually very familiar, for  
example, to modern consumers when they compare similar commodities of  
different brands and models for desired (and undesired) features,  
prices, etc.  Once one understands this general principle (multiplying  
the parameter variations to figure out the total possible  
combinations) and that this is the way this Sakharov-block puzzle  
works, the solution becomes completely obvious by just observing the  
parameters and counting their variations.  Since the solution seeks 4  
groups, and since there are no 4*1=4 solutions, the one and only  
possible other solution would be to find a 2*2=4 way of assembling the  
groups together.  And wallah!  There the solution is, plain as day  
once you see it - tall/flat and large/small.
In theory, if one understands this principle clearly, one could  
determine the different groups just by looking at the 22 blocks,  
counting and calculating the parameters and their variations by eye,  
and do so without picking up a single block.  However, since the  
nonsense words are arbitrarily assigned, it would still be necessary  
to pick up a block in each of 3 different groups to determine the  
precise names that correspond to each group.  There probably are  
people who could figure this all out just by staring at these blocks  
and arriving at this reasoning, but they would have to be a pretty  
experienced puzzle solver to do that in one shot, I would think.   
However, there are many very bright people associated with this list -  
anyone solved or seen the test solved in "one shot," so to speak?  (An  
interesting question to ask is, about those that do solve the test -  
which solve it **conceptually**, and which stumble on the solution as  
just a pseudoconcept?)
The question Mike and Paula discussed, and I think David raised, about  
what procedure or methodology does the test-giver use to guide the  
test-taker during the test, is especially interesting.  Which block do  
they overturn under what circumstances to show the test-taker the  
error of their ways during the test, and what other "hints" and  
"prods" to they provide as the test proceeds?   (The younger the  
child, the more creative prods are needed, from what Paula's  
reports!)  This question is interesting on two levels.  One,  
obviously, relates to how these prompts influence what the test-taker  
understands and does.  But here is another level to look at this from:  
**what concepts** are guiding the **test-giver** when they are giving  
their prompts?  (And if they are not being guided by "true concepts,"  
then what are they being guided by?)
My point in going into all this detail is to suggest that this  
parameter-counting principle is a concept, (or combination of  
concepts), and that the solution groups, which themselves are  
organized according to this principle, being completely derivative of  
this overall concept, are necessarily concepts as well.  Generalizing,  
I am suggesting that these are "concepts" within this experimentally- 
designed system in the same sense that the numbers 1, 2 and 3 are  
"concepts" within the number system.
Bik, cev, lag and mur, according to this reasoning, are the made-up  
names for specific concepts and are arbitrarily assigned - as are,  
ultimately, all words for the things they correspond to.  In this  
game, these four nonsense words correspond to the concepts flat-large,  
flat-small, tall-large, and tall-small, which are meaningful concepts  
within the game's rules.  These conceptual groups are an integral part  
of that puzzle's internal taxonomy and its overall conceptual system -  
even though this puzzle, in many ways, is just about as artificial,  
rule-based, experimental, arbitrary and trivial as you could probably  
invent and still get children and adults to make sense out of.  But  
lots of cool puzzles are kinda like that.  And this Vygotsky-Sakharov  
concept formation test really is a cool puzzle.
Well, that's my argument for calling these nonsense words "true  
concepts" in the Vygotskyan (not necessarily the Davydovian) sense.   
Thoughts?
- Steve




On Sep 11, 2009, at 1:14 PM, Jay Lemke wrote:

A small follow-up, having now read at least Andy's comments on  
Davydov, if not the Davydov itself.
I would agree very broadly with what Andy says, and highlight one  
point and note one that is perhaps underemphasized.
Maybe it's because of Davydov's view,  but it seems clear to me that  
LSV emphasizes very strongly and consistently the key role of verbal  
language, and so we ought really want to know more about exactly how  
the ways in which children and early adolescents use verbal  
languages changes as they come to mediate their activity more along  
the lines we might call acting-with-true-concepts.
What struck me as very important, that Andy emphasizes (and Davydov  
also?) is that the development of true concepts depends on their use  
in social institutions. This limits the relevance of artificial- 
concept experimental studies in ways that would not be apparent in a  
more purely cognitive science paradigm (or old fashioned empirical- 
concept ideology), because the similarity to natural true concepts  
is only logical-formal, and not also social-institutional. A lot of  
my own students tend to get this wrong, because they identify the  
social with the interpersonal, such that there is still a similarity  
(in the micro-social milieu of the experiment itself as a social  
activity). But not at the macro-social institutional level.
And here perhaps is also a clue to my query about how the modes of  
mediation differ across the historical cases (Foucault), the cross- 
cultural cases (Levi-Straus), the post-modern cases (Wittgenstein,  
Latour), and even the everyday true concept vs. formal scientific- 
mathematical true concept cases. The difference arises in and from  
the institutional differences. Could we perhaps combine LSV's  
insights into how this works in the developmental case (changes in  
the social positioning of the child/adolescent), L-S on the  
functioning of mytho-symbolic mediated activiity in rituals and  
social structuration processes, F on changes in the historical  
institutions (medieval-early modern), and L on heterogeneity of  
mediation in relation to heterogeneity of actant networks? to  
understand better how this institutional context and its processes  
play out?
I left out Wittgenstein, but he may help with an intermediate scale,  
not the large social institutions, but the game-like activities of  
which they are composed.
I'll be looking at Davydov to see what he offers in these terms.

JAY.


Jay Lemke
Professor (Adjunct)
Educational Studies
University of Michigan
Ann Arbor, MI 48109
www.umich.edu/~jaylemke





On Sep 11, 2009, at 5:51 AM, Andy Blunden wrote:

I have prepared a response to Davydov's book, but it is 4,000 words, so I have attached it in a Word document. But here is a synopsis.
Davydov claims that in his analysis of the Sakharov experiments,  
Vygotsky fails to demonstrate any real distinction between a true  
concept and an abstract general notion (what is usually and  
mistakenly taken for a concept in non-Marxist thought).
I claim that he has a point, but Vygotsky is guilty only of some  
unclarity and inconsistency in his language, and makes the  
distinction very clear. And Davydov should pay more attention to  
what Vygotsky says about the relationship.
Davydov works with a mistaken contrast between scientific concepts  
and the general notions derived from everyday life. Scientific  
concepts are by no means the only type of true concepts and  
everyday life is full of concepts.
Nonetheless, Davydov has a point. It is evident that Sakharov, the  
author of the orignal, oft-cited report evidently is guilty exactly  
as charged by Davydov. And no-one seems to have noticed!
Although Paula and Carol are consistent and correct in everything  
they say in their paper, they err on one occasion only when they  
cite Kozulin citing Hanfmann. It is as if people equate logical use  
of generalized empirical notions with conceptual thought, never in  
their own words, but only by means of citing someone else's words.
I think this is the legacy of a lack of clarity in Vygotsky's  
brilliance.
4,000 words attached. And apologies for not entering the discussion  
of Paula and Carol's paper earlier, but I was not clear in my own  
mind on these problems, and Davydov helped me get clear. Better  
late than never!
Andy
http://www.marxists.org/archive/davydov/generalization/
http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/concept-really-concept.htm
http://www.marxists.org/archive/vygotsky/works/comment/sakharov.htm
------------------------------------------------------------------------
Andy Blunden (Erythrós Press and Media) Orders: http://www.erythrospress.com/store/main.html#books

<concept-really- concept.doc>_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca
_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca
_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca