Dear David and Martin Thank you for your questions on wolves large and small - and the interest in the blocks which reveal them. I can think of few other forms of technology that continue to be in use unchanged since the turn of the last century - yet these humble little blocks continue to engage our attention and our discussion about subjects much larger than they (puts me in mind of David and Goliath...). A.1. My understanding of the "ontogenesis of concept formation" is that it is about the processes involved in the development of concepts from earliest childhood to adulthood. Vygotsky says that the form and content of a conceptual (or preconceptual) representation are determined by such elements as a developmental trend (the age of the subject), the genesis/history of the concept over time in the subject's mind, the history and situation in which the concept appears, and the signifying function of language on the content and form in themselves. (The attachment may illustrate my understanding of these points more clearly.) A.2. I think that concept formation without the "ontogenesis" refers to the things in A.1. above, but with less emphasis on the developmental trend: concept formation without the "ontogenesis" for me refers to the thinking strategies that adults would be more likely to invoke in coming to understand something new. And also when they encounter something beyond their own field of expertise - nuclear physics or rocket science - and when they use short-hand to create generalised representations of things (everyday concepts; concepts-for-ourselves-and-not-for-experts). In concept formation without the "ontogenesis", the signifying function of language would possibly also be augmented because adults (and adolescents) will tend use one system (like maths or ethics) to understand another. A.3. I don't imagine that Vygotsky's asking us to think about concept formation without changes in ontogenesis: in fact, quite the opposite. Changes are obviously par for the course in adults too - but not to the same degree as changes in the structure and role of the thinking modes of children. It seems to me that the thinking strategies and modes which feature in Chapter 5 are about A.1. and A.2. B. I suspect that "lupine behaviour" can't easily be separated from the "sheep's clothing" because pseudoconcepts superficially resemble "real" concepts in both role (what the word meaning does) and structure (how it's put together). Yet how long the wolf is likely to be kept from the door may not have been explicitly revealed by the blocks experiment (unless we conduct follow-ups in some way?) - yet I find that Vygotsky's references about the experimental procedure and its results to be sufficiently compelling to prevent me from "deep sixing" Chapter Five altogether. David and I do agree that the extent to which we can generalise these findings outside of the experimental situation is not clearly supported by research or clear links in Chapter Six and that Vygotsky frequently acknowledged the need for more investigation, ever cautious about the extent of his studies and the reality of (genetic forms coexisting as) geological strata. Yet I keep coming back to "the key" from page 146, and what I'd like to explore further about the Chapter Fivers in relation to scientific and everyday concepts (in more detail hopefully than the measures of generality of Chapter 6.6). Perhaps some of the key lies in unmasking pseudoconcepts: we need to catch a wolf on the move, yet, as you can see from the paper, they wear different kinds of wool, some thicker than others. I think the secret's somewhere in the abstraction, the generalisation, the juxtapositions, the signifying use of language - and the ability to use these consistently (for me, the participant in Figure 20 makes it very clear how easy it is to lose the thread...). C. It seems to me that functional equivalence on the part of a user who doesn't know any different would be relative and relational and in the eyes of the beholder not the holder: yet, irrespective of who perceives what and how, for me what these constructs are about is the movement towards how particular meanings are constructed. The blocks may not reveal the all of the complexities of processes involved in us coming to understand - and master - a range of concepts (not only nouns and adjectives, including Martin's analytical and dialectical concepts, and perhaps creative and imaginative ones too), but they do get us moving in a particular direction. C.1. David, you and I do agree on this: Pseudoconcepts and concepts have a functional equivalence in role - enabling communication - and a functional equivalence in structure - which most certainly does not equate to a similar structure, but to a structure which apparently functions in a way which makes it look like a conceptual structure. The dreams are very different indeed - even from heads on the same pillow. Concepts and pseudoconcepts deal with similar contents, but in different ways, because pseudoconcepts put things together according to different rules. The structures are very different - and yet, because meanings in the words around children have been established by the adults around them, the germinating seed of the concept-for-myself is contained within the concept-for-others and in-itself, just waiting for it to be grasped and mastered. In this vein, it seems to me that Martin's children's analytic and dialectical concepts could well have their roots, to varying degrees of complexity, in a tendency to link concrete, factual, and functional attributes rather than logical, abstract(ed), essential characteristics or principles; in an insensitivity to inconsistencies and contradictions; and in the functional rather than conceptual use of a system to compare or juxtapose one's actions against. So, hunting in packs concrete and factual alongside those which are abstract and logical reveals so much about differences and similarities in how we go to places and what we find along the way. Thank you, as always, David, for making me think about thinking. Talk again soon. Paula ps: A note in closing is this: what readers of the Wolves paper will notice is the absence of an explicit explanation of the solution to the problem posed by the blocks: this omission was quite deliberate. For those who've read Minick or Kozulin, for example, the solution appears to be so simple that it can evoke a "Yawn, yawn, so what?" type of response in the reader's mind. It was precisely this reaction that I wanted to avoid because it can make it easy to dismiss the blocks altogether. The simplicity of the solution (the double dichotomy) is a design feature of great genius (Sakharov's), and it really is seldom stumbled across in the first five minutes with the blocks. And then there's also Minick's rather bad press: in his introduction, he refers more times to Chapter 5 than to any other, and very little of this reference is flattering. These two factors taken together can lead - and perhaps have led - to these astonishing blocks being overlooked, if not forgotten in recent times. Because it's not just about blocks in strange experimental situations - it's about how we are able to respond to the method of double stimulation and there are as many ways of going about solving the problem of the blocks as there are people who engage with them. But only one (logical, guided) solution, irrespective of the range of hypotheses advanced by subjects in the course of their engagement with the blocks (despite the claims of modification studies for "multiple solution" approaches, eg, Fosberg's 1948 work which missed the point entirely and which resulted in 149 solutions and more). -----Original Message----- From: xmca-bounces@weber.ucsd.edu [mailto:xmca-bounces@weber.ucsd.edu] On Behalf Of David Kellogg Sent: 02 August 2009 03:35 PM To: Culture ActivityeXtended Mind Subject: Re: [xmca] Vygotsky, Saussure, and Wolves Speaking for myself, my silence had two causes. First of all, like Andy, I was rather awestruck by Martin's paragraphs on Marx's method, and like Martin himself I was reflecting on them. But secondly I was reading Paula and Carol's article, "Wolves in Sheep's Clothing" and reflecting on whether I should force my grads to read it next quarter. The first part of it contains the best synopsis of Vygotsky's sprawling, often contradictory presentation of the taxonomy of syncretic heaps, complexes, and preconceptual formations that I've ever read. Before I do that, though, I want to know the answer to the following questions on the first page of Paula and Carol's piece, which I think are actually related to Martin's questions about what work has been done to find out whether children and the researchers who do word meaning research are not "sleeping on one bed but having different dreams". a) In the abstract, Paula and Carol refer to the "ontogenesis of concept formation". What does the ontogenesis of concept formation mean? Does it mean the same thing as concept formation or does it mean the way in which concept formation changes in the ontogenesis of the child? b) "Lupine behavior" means conceptual FUNCTION. "Sheep's clothing" means that they are STRUCTURALLY similar to complexes. As Vygotsky says at the end of Chapter Seven, only the historical, genetic method can really reveal either. But the experimental method does not really test the history of concept use at all; Vygotsky saw it as a logical test which gives us the "essence of a genetic study in abstracted form" (see Minick translation, p. 146). This really gets us back to the "Strange Situation" question I asked over a year ago (which Vygotsky reverts to at the end of Chapter Six): to what extent CAN we extrapolate genetic processes from logical tests? This is what Martin is asking, and I really don't know the answer. I think Vygotsky changes his mind on this question somewhere between Chapter Five and Chapter Six. c) In the first paragraph, Paula and Carol discuss functional equivalence of pseudoconcepts and concepts. in some places, Vygotsky talks about EVERYTHING--including syncretic heaps--as the child's functional equivalent's of concepts, so in places Vygotsky simply means what is IN THE CHILD'S EYES functionally equivalent. But in other places he suggests that the pseudoconcept alone is in EVERY WAY functionally equivalent to the concept (and therefore indistinguishable, even using questions). Obviously, functional "equivalence" must be relative, relational, and in the eyes of the beholder. I think that the key is that pseudoconcepts and concepts are equivalent in function but they are not equivalent in structure, because the structure depends on the SYSTEM and of course the SYSTEM is quite different. For example, self-directed speech can be functionally different from social speech but structurally very similar at three, and still in the spoken aloud mode even at seven. Form follows function, but sometimes at quite a distance; exaptation means that we adopt things functionally first and only later adapt them structurally. d) Finally, I note that the word "pseudoconcept" is a good example of how adults as well as children have different dreams when they use the same word (or, to adopt Paula, Carol and Lev Semyonovich's expression, how they wear different clothing when they hunt in the same pack). It's not actually Lev Semyonovich's coinage at all; it's from Stern. But Vygotsky is always hollowing out other people's words, and placing his own candles within. David Kellogg Seoul National University of Education PS: Martin, I'm a little confused by your refs to folk psychology. In T&S Chapter Four (and also in Mescharyakov 2007, which Paula and Carol reference) we see that folk psychology and folk physics do NOT refer to the child's own concepts, but rather to everyday thinking taken from the child's social situation of development; they are the inter-mental forms of the functional equivalents of concepts tht we find intra-mentally in the children. dk --- On Sat, 8/1/09, Martin Packer <packer@duq.edu> wrote: From: Martin Packer <packer@duq.edu> Subject: Re: [xmca] Vygotsky and Saussure To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu> Date: Saturday, August 1, 2009, 8:19 AM I'm going to use the silence as an opportunity to reflect on my own message - Reading what I wrote about Marx's method again in the context of the discussion here it occurs to me that Marx, like Vygotsky, was writing about the changing character of word-meaning. I'd not thought about Capital in quite that way before. On the other hand, LSV doesn't, to my knowledge, draw a distinction between children's analytic concepts and their dialectical concepts. Has anyone out there worked on this? (Paula?) I'm currently reading the literature on young children's categories (folkbiology, folkpsychology), and much of this research seems to assume exactly the equivalence of adult and child word-meaning that LSV called into question, so the topic is important. For example, the researcher names for the child a picture of an animal, and then asks a question (Does X have a heart?) to which the child can reply only yes or no. The characteristics of the child's 'categories' are inferred on the basis of an assumed equivalence of word-meaning. Martin _______________________________________________ xmca mailing list xmca@weber.ucsd.edu http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca _______________________________________________ xmca mailing list xmca@weber.ucsd.edu http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca
Attachment:
Some Vygotsky on concept formation and Sakharov's 19 points.doc
Description: MS-Word document
_______________________________________________ xmca mailing list xmca@weber.ucsd.edu http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca