Re: Chasing the Object

From: Ben Reshef family (victor@kfar-hanassi.org.il)
Date: Thu Jul 03 2003 - 08:28:25 PDT


The discussions here have been most interesting. They have helped considerably to clarify my understanding and expression of issues important to Cultural Historical theory, general and computational. And, they have focussed my attention on at least one major theoretical issue (that of authority) that I more or less glossed over in previous thinking. Jay's commentary on my posting was particularly important in this regard and I would like to share some of the new research directions that it has inspired. Some of the commentary is a bit long and I plead guilty of a certain rustiness in my expressive skills and thank those of you who review it for your patience. One fairly long comment is devoted to the problem of distinction between objectification of tools and of social relations. The distinction between the two is important to the very fabric of Material Cultural Historical theory and deserves more development than was presented in the course of the discussion.
Anyway, many thanks to all the participants.
Yours,
Victor

----- Original Message -----
  From: Jay Lemke
  To: xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
  Sent: Wednesday, June 25, 2003 5:35 AM
  Subject: Re: Chasing the Object

  Continuing the dialogue on this topic, I'm sending some notes I made on Victor's recent posting. Obviously there is a lot more to be said, and I thank him for offering such stimulating discussions, connecting the topic of material-ideal-objectifications to larger issues of social organization of complex systems.

  I have inserted my notes between paragraphs of Victor's posting, after copying it to WORD and back again, so please excuse any formatting problems ... I have also highlighted some key points in the original. Please note that I wrote these comments mostly for myself, but thought others might like to see them, so they are not quite in my usual dialogical style and I don't have the time right now to edit them ...

  From: "Ben Reshef family" <victor@kfar-hanassi.org.il>
  To: <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>

  Subject: Re: Chasing the Object
  Date: Sun, 22 Jun 2003 19:22:16 +0200

          

  Dear Jay,
  Your observation that the failure to explain the persistence through
  objectification exposes the shortcomings of agent based and other bottoms up
  models, such as Ethnomethodology, J. Shotter's writings, and Newman and
  Holtzman's work, is exactly to the point. The building of an agent model for
  a HDM explication of social organization quickly exposed this weakness and
  pressed for modifications to rectify this flaw. The solution that I applied
  is tripartite, consisting of three separate but related matters; authority,
  the abstract ideal object, and the tolerance for internal diversity imparted
  to systems by authority and abstract ideal objectifications.

  1) . Authority: One of the most important considerations in S. Kaufman's
  analyses of order in biological systems [Kaufman 1993,The Origins of Order:
  Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution, 1995, At Home in the Universe:
  The Search for Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity.] is the double
  issue of error and complexity catastrophe. Brown and Eisenhardt [1998
  Competing on the Edge: "Strategy as structured chaos"] introduced the issue
  and their definition of it seems to me to be the best.
  "Error catastrophe or extinction mutagenesis is a theory borrowed from
  bio-genetics that describes a situation in which a high mutation rate
  introduces so many errors into the system that it cannot adapt well because
  it cannot distinguish useful variants from errors."
  It cannot distinguish them fast enough because of the generational timelag inherent in selectional processes.

  And, "In the extreme,
  the system becomes grid locked by too many interconnections. These ties
  constrain the system and prevent adaptation. The result is a 'complexity
  catastrophe." In general informationally poor interactional systems are poor
  innovators and are especially susceptible to complexity catastrophe when
  encountering changeable environments.
  This is a version of the "requisite variety" argument of Ashby. If the system does not have enough internal informational variety it cannot respond to external stresses. Of course any system locks up if the number of constraints from interaction exceeds the residual degrees of freedom. There is insufficient residual plasticity for adaptation.

       Human interactional systems would appear to be the most plagued by
  error catastrophe, considering the relative richness of "Cartesian" object
  experience possible to the individual person in any temporal local
  condition.
  Semiotic imagination makes possible a faster rate of production of internally generated novelty compared to the slow rate of selectional correction of the introduced 'errors". Unfortunately the effects are cumulative and one gets an acceleration of novelty production in human social systems, as we are especially seeing today.

  The capacity for individuals to learn from each other mitigates
  considerably the dangers of error catastrophe; but not enough to explain the
  evolution of complex human culture.
  There seem to be two kinds of learning here. Local transmission of information about corrections and collective analysis to identify errors.

  Even simple experiments with a small
  collectivity of interacting, learning agents with moderately high perceptual
  capacities show that while stochastic convergence of performance is highly
  likely for any one interaction session, the agents quickly diverge once the
  session is finished and a new meeting between them involves a repetition of
  consensus search.
  This is, as Victor says, an effect and weakness of bottom-up models in which only negotiated consensus among individual agents can produce collective coherence of behavior.

    It is both a weakness and strength. Since you have pointed out its weakness, I'll address its strengths. The failure of small collectivities of interacting agent with moderately high perceptual capacities to arrive at persistent consensus indicates that enduring social order must be based on more than recurrent interaction. Our solution to this problem was to introduce a means whereby agents can "save" repeated dialogues and to select their responses to interactional situations in accordance with the amount of "saves" for all dialogues relevant to the situation. It is this mechanism (roughly analogous to habit) that serves as the basis for our general theory of asymmetrical interaction and authority. (See below).

  Besides, the convergence process tends to be a lengthy
  one - it grows in duration with the expansion of agent perceptual capacity -
  and guarantees that agent interactions can neither be quick (say in an
  emergency situation) nor be complex. Time restrictions on the period for
  consensus formation simply result in many interaction breakdowns due to
  error catastrophe.
  Yes, it is exactly the timescale problem that matters here, and as Victor notes it gets worse as there are more parameters to negotiate "agreement" on. It's just too slow for survival under the eventual conditions.

    Again, the "saving" mechanism and the general theory of asymmetrical interaction and authority lessen and even eliminate this problem.

       A search for more effective means for reducing error catastrophe led to
  introduction of two additional mechanisms into the system: conviction or
  commitment and concurrence.
  a) Conviction: Simply put, conviction is the preference of agents to
  perform what they have already learned and to perform what they've learned
  most often. Could also be called "habit" or "automatism"??

  Habit, yes. Automatism, no. Habit can be replaced by new experience, automatism cannot.

  b) Concurrence: In the same discourse mode, concurrence is the preference of
  agents to perform in accordance with the performances of the agents with
  whom they interact and especially in accordance with the performances of the
  agents with whom they regularly interact. The herd instinct, or cogent sociality.
  Adaptation or responsiveness to the behavior of others would be more fitting.

  Conviction and Concurrence are in many respects antithetical; the former
  being a product of the history of personal experience (even if a sociogenic
  one) while the latter is a product of immediate apperception of collective
  activity. This neatly reproduces the modern Western dilemma of individual choice vs. collective need. Perhaps we should be a bit suspicious of it for this reason.

  Firstly, this is not a strictly Western dilemma. A good deal of Japanese dramatic tragedy is based on this dilemma, it is often cited in Chinese history, popular and official, as the cause for personal and social disaster, and it is characteristic of hero crises in epic poetry world-wide. Second, the antithesis between conviction and concurrence is not presented here as a dilemma, but rather as a dialectic from which emerges authority as an incorporation of both conviction and concurrence in a new interactional relation (see below). This implies that conviction (habit as you put it) and concurrence (responsive adaptation to the behavior of others) are distinctly different kinds of operations, which is an assertion that stands as a direct challenge to the still very popular game theory-based model of sociality founded on "the prisoners' dilemma" paradigm (Axelrod 1984 The Evolution of Cooperation).

  The synthetic mechanism that emerges from conviction and
  concurrence and transforms them into a single system is Authority: the
  personalization of concurrence and the collectivization of conviction.
  Ah, this is much better than just having a tension between conviction and concurrence dispositions. But how exactly is it implemented?

          It is considerably easier to implement conviction and concurrence into the computational model than to present a theoretical justification. The "saving to memory" mechanism described above can represent both habit and identification of cumulative public opinion and the logical operators of the program (inferred generalization, ordered memory systems, and so on) insure that conviction and concurrence are expressed in one or another objectification mode.

       The theory expressed by these mechanisms demands more expansive treatment than can be given here, especially since it challenges the epistemology, mechanics and physics of theories of the roots of social behavior of a very large sector of the scientific community. Putting it most briefly, conviction (habit) and concurrence (adaptive response to others behavior) are distinctive evolutes emergent from the decline of instinct (rule based) behavior, i.e. that of social insects etc. From the dialectical interaction of conviction and adaptive responsiveness emerge mechanisms of social order such as personal and public dominion. Authority itself emerges from the dialectical relation between dominion and objectification. It appears to me that the evolution of authority shares many roots with the evolution of objectification. In essence they are both the product of the same paradox of the autonomously adapting individual who adapts to extant conditions by coordinating his behavior with others of his kind.

  Authority introduced into the model the principle of instructing as well as
  learning, albeit in a fairly simplistic and passive manner (akin to the way
  a Tai Chi master disciplines an errant pupil, i.e. by simply not responding
  to performance that does not conform to the convictions of the teacher). By
  introducing even the most simplistic teaching modes into the model we give a
  powerful boost to the reduction of error catastrophe at a drastically
  reduced cost in time and energy.

  This is very reminiscent for me of a proposal I made quite a long time ago in a different context that the "teaching instinct" was as fundamental to sociality as the "learning drive". They are of course complementary. We are as much driven to provide the information needed by others (esp. for instance children and newcomers) as we are in other circumstances to seek out that information. Children trigger our teaching instincts as part of their learning drive. Interesting to think how far such a principle generalizes.

  2) Abstract ideal objectifications: The second issue involved in the
  introduction of object persistence in a bottoms up model of social
  organization involved the integration of the system with the Vygotskian
  scheme of dialectical development of mental practices and with Ilyenkov's
  conceptualisation of "Ideal objects" (or "formations" as I sometimes call
  them).

    Instinct is going a bit far, don't you think? I prefer an interpretation of the "need to know" and "need to teach" as the product of the absence of rule-based (instinctive) behavior among humans.

       In modelling the Vygotskian modes of mental practice it was discovered
  that development through the complexes stages involve a not unsurprising
  progressive decline in the creativity of transformation of experience into
  objects and an equivalent increase in the connectivity and complexity of
  mental practice.

  What was less expected and no less interesting was that
  the burgeoning systems of associated facts characterising the more developed
  forms of thinking in complexes (epitomized by pseudo conceptual thinking)
  unify large bodies of experience at the cost of the flexibility of the
  practice to adapt to temporal, local conditions.

  This is best exemplified
  by Piaget [1965. The moral judgment of the child.] and Kohlberg's [Power, F.
  C., Higgins, A., & Kohlberg, L. 1989. Lawrence Kohlberg's Approach to Moral
  Education.] observations of the moral aspects of children's play in the
  middle stage of the age grade. ( At this stage arguments concerning game
  rules are frequent and extensive and are very often resolved by force or by
  boycotting the non-conformists. Clearly where complex performances are
  regarded as strictly rule-based facts, negotiated settlements are difficult
  if not impossible alternatives to partial or total breakdowns in
  interactional relations.

       The abstract mode of thinking represents a synthesis of analytic and
  synthetic practice whereby large quantities of objects (or performances) may
  be variously classified in accordance with features shared between them.

  The groups formed through abstraction are strictly defined by the common
  element shared by all members, and unlike the case with factual classes, a
  member of an abstract category can be regarded as being a part of any number
  of abstract categories if other of its features so warrant it.
  Relevant here is Watanabe's theorem in logic, which reminds us that we have to assign VALUE priorities to features in order to decide according to which similarities and differences categories are to be preferentially constructed, among all possible categorizations of multi-featured elements.

  Truly abstract thought modes enable establishment of vast systems of connected
  objects, yet provides a means for great system flexibility and provides a
  firm basis for the formation of complex, persistent objects and object
  systems.
  But in a sense this only pushed the dilemma up one level, to negotiations regarding values. Here flexibility is also needed, but if we are not to get too high and too fast levels of schizmogenesis (ala Bateson), we also need a countervailing push toward value consensus, one that very likely must come from "above" not in the sense of personal authority/arianism, but in the sense of cultural traditions, or more likely a heteroglossia of interdependent subcultural value-systems.

        Clearly any model that purports to simulate interaction involving abstract objectification must by definition draw information from a much wider social environment than that of the immediate encounter. These abstract objectifications may be resident in the personal archives of the participants in the encounter as part of each individual's accumulated experience, but all of them have been acquired in the course of prior social interaction. Encounters involving participants whose prior experience has been acquired within the same cultural traditions or the same multiplicity of interdependent subcultural traditions will tend to sustain those traditions. Still most cultural tradition, even that of small fairly isolated communities, is rarely monolithic, the multiplicity of interdependent traditions often hiccups, and so it is to be expected that there will be some variation in the array of objectifications in the personal archives of members of even the most culturally monolithic of communities. Some thirty years of personal experience in such a community and at least some ethnographic material on small isolated communities tend to confirm this view (I'm thinking here particularly of an interesting monograph on the expression of current internal political conflicts in Zuni Pueblo through different version of myth - published in the 50's in AA). So, while direct encounters may well preserve most of the objectifications of the tribe they may also include elements of conflict reflecting both the differential experiences of the participants in the encounter and the general sogginess that characterizes all human organization.

       The presence of conflict in an encounter, even where the issues at stake are "trivial," will engender exercises of authority. Since exercise of authority is both personal - someone does it to someone else - and communal - it's as effective as the social clout of the collectivity it represents - the issue of personal versus communal authority is not an issue here.

        Ilyenkov's [1977, The concept of the Ideal] concept of the ideal
  object as reflexive abstraction of social interaction (the objectification
  of interactional performance systems) imparts purpose and value to
  objectified material experience. "Human aims are nothing but the material
  process and outcome of activity in ideal form. The ideal image is the object
  of production converted into an internal image, as a need, as a drive and as
  purpose" [Marx 1973 Grundrisse].
  So here we in fact do have the importance of values and purposes. Interesting to think how values, as well as practices are embodied in objects and formation. Obvious (post Bakhtin) for the case of discourses, but perhaps less so for the case of material tools and artifacts. We have a notion of affordances for the relation to practices, but we need a complementary notion to also link material tools and artifacts to value systems, particularly values relevant to resolution of social conflict, or to prescribing the "right" way to do things in cases where there are clearly multiple possible practices and not having some consensus about them would lead to great risks for community survival. Perhaps the answer here lies in the combinations in cultures of tools/artifacts WITH discourses and activities that carry a sense of "rightness" with their performances. One can note the great importance attached to "right performance" of symbolic rituals. We interpret this instrumentally from our own cultural perspective, but that may project our view too much. There is value, essential value, for a community in attaching to activities of significance a strong community consensus about the right way to do them, regardless of immediate effects. This in turn frequently becomes an arena of discussion and negotiation, itself a model for the survival process of the community, and more importantly, an opportunity to renew the meta-value principles, which are often unstated and implicit, that guide the outcomes of the negotiations about what is the right performance. It is having ways to get to consensus about values that matters most, even if there is continuing diversity of values (cf. heteroglossia) and conflict over policies, actions, etc.

  Regarding the underlined sentences. This is part of the point of Ilyenkov's The Concept of the Ideal (1977). Material tools and artefacts are integrated into social life by according their use and products some sort of social purpose. Social purpose is a function of human intercourse and is not implicit to the tool. Even in the class of cases you present ".values (concerning tools and artifacts) relevant to resolution of social conflict, or to prescribing the "right" way to do things in cases where there are clearly multiple possible practices and not having some consensus about them would lead to great risks for community survival." The issue at stake is not the tool, but the coordination of work practices to attain socially established goals. Take, for example, the "right use" of the penultimate tool, speech. A pragmatist explanation of the social value of speech would attend to the tool itself, and assert that speech is designed to insure that "one is understood by others" and that it is this goal that justifies learning "proper speech." Understanding "proper speech" as an expression of social purpose would attend to the representational function of kinds of "proper speech" as signifiers of social solidarity and exclusivity, it's relationship to extant social structures and so on. The pragmatic argument fails since it regards understanding, of all things, as having no real relationship to social intercourse! The origin of this failure is the treatment of the abstraction, speech, as having a material reality other than its manifestations in social intercourse. It just doesn't happen.

        Even the functional value of a more humble tool such as the hammer must be understood through social signifiers, i.e. Ideal objectifications. Except as the iconic representation of the working class on the flag of the USSR the hammer itself is not a social signifier, but it certainly does play a part in attaining social objectives such as construction of a long conference table whose elegance and obvious costliness will serve to signify the status, wealth and power of the institution for which it was made. And what of the proper use of the hammer? In this case we would have to search for its social value in the economic relations between hammer user, his employer, the purveyor of the materials for table construction and the purchaser of the table as signified mostly by the various documents (banknotes, paychecks, contracts, and registries of accounts). In a market economy the hammer user would be expected by his employer to use methods that would minimize costs of materials and labor and maximize the final impression the table would have on the purchaser. The hammerer might have other considerations, some consistent with those of his employer such as the desired impression the table is to have on the purchaser (at least in regards to nail placement and insertion) and some not, such as the value of his labor and the amount of time required to produce a highly crafted table. Note that the hammer itself is not a social object, even though it is very much a part of the social intercourse, and that the rightness of its use is intimately connected with the specific social conditions of its use. Clearly, the right way to use a hammer when banging together 20 or 30 crates for sending machine tools will be very different than that appropriate for making a fine conference table.

   

  All the representations
  that refer to social practice, colours, flags, and written law are serve as
  reinforcement for both the objects and the organization of social relations
  that generate and maintain them. As P Jones writes:
  "This, indeed is the special and vital function which ideal forms fulfil in
  human life-activity: they allow the goals, aims, drives, purposes,
  strategies and forms of action and cooperation of social humanity to be
  represented outside of, prior to and independently of the real activities
  which engender them:" [2000: "Symbols, Tools and Ideality in Ilyenkov"]
  This is certainly correct, but perhaps it is not the whole story .our ideal-objects, the material objectifications of community values, are themselves embedded in discourses and activities which explicitly raise issues of right performance, the values which guide right performance, and the normally inexplicit meta-values and meta-practices that enable consensus about values and policies, i.e. about "right performance". I think that the paradigm in mind in Jones' analysis is building solidarity for rapid collective consensus response in emergencies (like war). But we need our model to also consider the functions that occur with respect to longer-term, less acute maintenance of the community's ability to respond to slower, but no less profound demands for change/adaptive response.

  I certainly agree with you here, the problem of discourse and activities that are reflexively related to ideal objects, which are themselves reflexive objectifications of social interaction, indicates that at least some human behavior involves much more recursiveness than the simple reflexivities dealt with by Ilyenkov. After all, what we are doing here, the practice of social science and social philosophy, is the paramount case of recursive social behavior, and a truly legitimate social philosophy should be able to account for its own practice no less than for other forms of social behavior.

  3) System tolerance:

   Authority and abstract objects, especially abstract ideal objects, preserve
  object persistence on the smallest as well as the largest scales of social
  organization.
  This is extremely important. Note particularly the they can BRIDGE across timescales.

  They are, therefore, equally effective in explaining how
  long-lived practices and related objectifications may be produced in
  directly observable interpersonal interaction as in historical developments
  involving many such interpersonal events. Surely many practices and
  objectifications are products of many interactional encounters and can never
  be traced to a single case of social intercourse or even to the history of
  social interaction of a single group of people. On the other hand, even in
  this age of mass media, the basic unit of significant social activity is the
  encounter or interactional event and even the most complex and largest
  scaled social organizations can only be realized through the interpersonal
  activity of those whose practices form and enact them. It would be very
  strange if we could only find the mechanisms responsible for object
  persistence outside the interactional event.
  I certainly agree that we need to examine the role of ideal-objects on and across many scales, both extensional (numbers of participants) and temporal (short to longer term processes). They, and the activities in which they are embedded (including discursive activities), emerge collectively (in their material construction, but especially in their social-cultural significance) across many instances of more local interactions, as Victor notes. But they function both at those local scales AND at more macro-social and historical ones. Just HOW this happens, and how to model it, is still an important and open question.

  Several linkages between micro and macro-social scales are already available for investigation. One of these is the way abstract objectifications serve as a bridge between micro and macro-social formations discussed above. Another interesting avenue of research into this issue is the fairly new mathematical work on small-world networks (Watts and Strogatz 1998 "Collective dynamics of small-world networks" Nature).

  The response is not complete and is telegraphic in some passages , but I
  think it covers the field. .

  With Regards,
  Victor

    ----- Original Message -----
    From: "Jay Lemke" <jaylemke@umich.edu>
    To: <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
    Sent: Saturday, June 21, 2003 5:07 PM
    Subject: Re: Chasing the Object

>
> Two interesting sets of issues seem to be accumulating around our
> object-discussion ... one, emphasized by Harry D., is the complementarity
> of object production and community production; the other, reinforced by
    Ben
> R., is the question of the ephemeral collective emergence of objects in
> activity.
>
> I like Harry's making the connection to Bernstein, and I think that his
> sophisticated sociological view of the complementarity of community
> processes and instructional or productive ones is indeed very close both
    to
> CHAT and to the complementarity issues raised by Foot's article.
> Bernstein's core theoretical analysis places a lot of importance on the
> classical sociological notion of the "division of labor", and so on the
> issue of co-ordination and integration of efforts in a community, so that
> the whole adds up to a functional unity. This is also the key question
    that
> Ben raises by reference to agent-based models of ant behavior. It happens
> that such agent-based models are now being widely applied to human social
> systems, asking the key question: how do complex collective productions
> result from the unplanned, or emergent coordination of relatively simple
> templates for interactive behavior?
>
> But there is a big difference here between Bernstein's, or Marx's,
> sociological analysis and agent-based models: the issue of persistence
> through objectification. Ben notes that historical-dialectical models, in
> their more revolutionary moments, emphasize the transitory character of
> social formations. But every social formation has some set of
> characteristic timescales (for inception, for maintenance cycles, for
> action cycles, for change, for demise), and what is ephemeral on one
> timescale (decades or centuries) may be quite stable and persistent on
> another (hours or months). The agent-based models are purely "bottom-up"
> social models; they do not include the creation of new objects that have
> material persistence on longer timescales and which can mediate across
> scales (the way, for example, a material report or architectural plan
> persists over years and participates in readings and doings over minutes
    or
> days). Even ants build "burrows" that have material persistence and lend a
> kind of collective memory and behavioral affordances to short-term doings
> of the colony.
>
> Bernstein did not, so far as I know (please someone say if he did) address
> the issue of the grounds of persistence of human social-behavioral
> patterns, such as the instructional and regulatory discourses of
> educational or other institutions. He did doubtless make use of the notion
> of persistent social formations, and indeed his famous codes or coding
> orientations, linked to social-class differentiated participation in
> socialization activities, are among these. His model is not purely
> bottom-up. It is also top-down in the sense that larger-scale persistent
> features of the material conditions of social organization (e.g. the
> division of wealth as well as the division of labor) influence human
> development (e.g. learning in school). These social formations may well be
> the products of individual human agency, collectively organized in the
> past, but materially persistent into each individual's present. But this
> just shows, I think, that purely bottom-up models (e.g. ethnomethodology,
> or agent-based social modeling) are incomplete if they do not provide for
> persistent material objects and other forms of larger-scale, longer-time
> productions that in turn influence the ways in which at shorter
    timescales,
> collective activity is organized emergently from agent choices.
>
> Ben also very helpfully elaborated further on the Objekt vs. Gegenstand
> distinction, and in particular made very clear, as I had suggested, that
> for LSV and in the CHAT tradition, ideality arises not from construction
    by
> the individual mind as such, but from meaningful function in collective
> activity. I think, though, that he is a bit too pessimistic about the
> impossibility of studying ephemeral multi-faceted organizing objects of
> activity. If we over-emphasize the bottom-up aspect of object formation,
> this may seem to be the case. But if we recognize that by virtue of their
> (and our) materiality, Objects in the special CHAT sense are likely to
    also
> have some scale of temporal persistence, and some limits to the rates at
> which they change, mutate, evolve, etc., then the problem is more
> tractable. I certainly agree that if we see activity as organized around
> such Objects, the objects are dynamic (but not capricious or chaotic), and
> they are also multi-faceted, including contradictory facets as seen by
> differently positioned participants in the activity. If we ask: Is there
> one common Object?, we may be disappointed. But if we ask instead: is
    there
> an organized system of coordinated or complementary Objects? one which
> embodies and affords the organization and coordination of the activity
> itself among the manifold actions of its participants? then I think we
    must
> be able to find such a material organizational framework, scaffold, or
> "motive" (motif?) for an activity.
>
> Perhaps we need to push a bit further with the idea of complementarity
> between social process and activity products. The CHAT tradition begins I
> think from a paradigm of activity centered, in Marx, on productive
    labor --
> i.e. to activity that is organized around producing a material product.
> That product "exists" already for the participants in the activity in
    large
> part from its previous production and circulation in the community: most
> productive labor is about producing more of something that has already
> existed. It is because we participate in the social activities in which
    the
> products we wish to make have meaning for us that we are able to, and are
> motivated to, produce more of these products. We also usually need the
> original sample of the material product, as an object, or as a template,
    or
> symbolically represented in plans-for-making, or by tools-for-making ...
    in
> order to have successful production. Here we have the most stable kind of
> organizing "object": the object of re-production. And here also we have
    the
> most stable kind of community: one that reproduces itself in order to
> reproduce the objects that make it possible. Here also is the simplest
    form
> of the complementarity between community-building and object-producing
> activity. I think one can hear in this simple account many parallels with
> Bernstein's analysis.
>
> Bernstein of course went far beyond this simplest case, to consider social
> class reproduction through education, where the material object is some
    set
> of dispositions in the people so educated (and he recognized the useful
> link here to Bourdieu's formulation). People, or at least people of a
> certain kind, are also material objects of productive activity. But we
    also
> cannot lose sight of ephemerality and change. Too often reproductionist
> models also do not take into account the multiple timescales and
> contradictions that are generative of change in activity and communities.
> What happens when a community that sets out to produce one kind of object
> finds that the very existence of this object, or some feature of the
> community which is needed to create such an object, suggests the
> desirability of a further object? One could see this as a simple form of
> the revolutionary dialectic itself: the class conditions needed to produce
> the industrial objects of early capitalism propose changes in the
    relations
> of the community (more just distribution of profit), and the objects
> themselves may become a means to this end (printed broadsides, mass
> produced weapons). As the object of the community's activities becomes
    less
> the alienated industrial objects as such, and more the social relations of
> the community itself, a dialectic is engendered in which new kinds of
> material objects are needed to mediate the new kind of community, and the
> conditions of production of these new objects may again suggest further
> changes in the organization of the community. We move from a
> reproductionist model to an evolution-revolution model.
>
> In this formulation, as I believe in CHAT generally, the motor of change
    is
> the linkage between changing communities and changing product-objects.
    That
> link occurs in collective-productive-reflective activity. Ideality arises
> not just in social-functional meaning-in-activity, but more essentially in
> the critical-reflexive moments of activity, those in which we forge the
> material and value relations among our aims, our object-products, and the
> nature of our own community.
>
> JAY.
>
> At 04:48 PM 6/21/2003 +0200, you wrote:
> >I'm afraid that my comments about B. Robinson's distinction between
    objekt
> >and gegenstand were not clear (16 June 2003). If so I apologize for being
> >unnecessarily cryptic. The problem here is to provide a short and clear
    set
> >of comments
> >on the article that accurately reflects my general approach to the issue.
> >I,m not really sure if there is in this forum any consensus concerning
    these
> >issues so For those who are interested I'm sending an attachment that
    shows
> >how, or better, where I link the object and instrumental activity into
    CHAT.
> >The differences between my model and the AT model are, as I hope are made
> >clear in the attachment, are less a matter of basic theoretical
    differences
> >than they are of research approach.
> >
> > And now some comments on the Foot article:
> > If we were to choose a single feature that characterises historical
> >dialectical materialism, we would have to settle on the transitory
    character
> >of virtually every aspect of culture. Marx and Engels and most of their
> >followers regarded this feature of HDM as the scientific justification
    for
> >social revolution. Actually, for HDM the ephemeral character of culture
> >goes much deeper than this. Lurking behind the theory is the recognition
> >that human culture is a matter of more or less temporary accommodations
> >between interacting individuals and is never, ever frozen into the kinds
    of
> >rule based organization that characterises our less intellectually gifted
> >neighbours: ants, dogs and even dolphins.
> > Seen in this light, the object, be it material or ideal, is likely
    to
> >be different for every person sharing it, different for every case of
    social
> >intercourse, and different for every investigator researching the
> >individuals and interactions which share the object. Variation of the
> >properties of the object may include changes in kind as well as changes
    in
> >descriptive features. Take, for example, Marx and Engel's theories
> >concerning the basic definition of capitalism. The transformation of all
> >valuation of worth to that of the market (the objectification of all
> >relations as trade and all experience as commodity) is seen by them as a
> >product of the conversion of money (an ideal object representing the
> >performance of exchange) from an abstracted ideal object that links many
> >diverse interactional situations into a reified abstraction or material
> >object (they would call it a fetish) that defines interactional
    situations.
> >So for HDM the object, in its features and even in its general relation
    to
> >experience, is like the electron a very slippery thing indeed.
> > So how do we research the object? We can't, or at least not
    directly.
> >We can incorporate into our models the various ways the participants in
    the
> >interaction/s researched objectify the experiences and interactional
    systems
> >of interest, we can examine how these diversities are influenced and
    changed
> >by the interchanges that arise in the course of interaction, and we can
> >compare the "before and after" to discover the cumulative effects of the
> >interactions on the objectifications of the participants; but in all
    these
> >researches we a compelled to regard "the object" as an entity
    characterised
> >by a range of possible features and relations to experience. To carry
    the
> >electron analogy a bit further, the object should be regarded as a
    cluster
> >of possible features and relationships much as the electron is regarded
    as
> >occupying a cloud of possible positions.
> > The view of the transitory nature of the object presented here is
> >fairly close to that of the Foot analysis of EARWARN. This is
    particularly
> >the case with his notion of the essential uncatchability of the object.
> >"Although object conceptions can be observed and identified empirically,
    the
> >object-engaged and enacted yet always unfinished, simultaneously material
> >and ideal-is in its essence "uncatchable." I do wonder, however, whether
    he
> >even comes close to a thorough exposition of the diversity of
> >objectifications by which EARWARN was identified and through which
    EARWARN
> >was enacted. While we have a good representation in the paper as to the
> >character and evolution of the object as it was manifested in
    relationships
> >between researchers, between directors and between directors and
> >researchers, it is gives little information concerning the character and
> >evolution of the object in relations between directors and the funding
> >agency and no information about how the program was regarded by the
> >researched population (the potential troublemakers). He does not even
> >mention if these latter participants in the program were even aware of
> >EARWARN's existence. I suspect that if he had researched the
    participants
> >in EARWARN that were external to the research bureaucracy: the funding
> >agency and the researched population, he himself would have adopted the
    view
> >that there was in actuality no common object, EARWARN, during the period
    of
> >this study-that EARWARN was just a shell covering the individual goals of
> >its participants and may well have produced an even more interesting
    paper
> >than he did.
> >
> >
> >
> >-----
>
>
> Jay Lemke
> Professor
> University of Michigan
> School of Education
> 610 East University
> Ann Arbor, MI 48104
>
> Tel. 734-763-9276
> Email. JayLemke@UMich.edu
> Website. www.umich.edu/~jaylemke
>

  Jay Lemke
  Professor
  University of Michigan
  School of Education
  610 East University
  Ann Arbor, MI 48104

  Tel. 734-763-9276
  Email. JayLemke@UMich.edu
  Website. www.umich.edu/~jaylemke



This archive was generated by hypermail 2b29 : Fri Aug 01 2003 - 01:00:08 PDT