[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Re: [xmca] The strange situation



Martin, after looking over Ch 5 an Ch 6 again, and looking at your post, I can see how nicely you are pulling out the two kinds of explanations LSV uses to explain concept development, and that you actually are laying a very good foundation to attack Ch 6.

Having looked over both Ch 5 and 6 again, here are some notes on what I see as the key difference between the two chapters, focusing mostly on Ch 6 sect 6. David's recent posts helped me quite a bit in seeing this in a new light.

As you know, the explanatory line that Vygotsky develops in Ch 6 sect 6 is along the line of the processes of abstraction and generalization, where he explains his concept of the **relations of generality**. This is where he discusses the law of concept equivalence and the measure of generality, using the globe model.

(That globe model - where all the latitudes and longitudes, meridians and parallels are reversed! Was that really Vygotsky's doing, or was it perhaps his publisher? It is a strange error, to be repeated over many sentences, and also pages later. A few years ago we discussed this on xmca and it was confirmed this error is also in Russian.)

What I think is very important in this theory of the relations of generality is that a **developmental** theory of concept formation emerges.

This theory of the relations of generality reveals something hinted at, but not systematically understood in Ch 5 - the **transformability** of the internal systems within concept formation processes into one another. This is they to it becoming a developmental theory.

These concept systems, or structures of generalization, or levels of concept formation (Vygotsky sure loved to tinker with variations in his terms, didn't he?), according to the theory of the relations of generality, are composed of the dialectical relations of abstraction and concreteness, the general and the specific, and the object and the idea. Those are the essential elements and dialectical oppositions that Vygotsky builds this theory with. These are, I think, what Vygotsky has in mind with his frequent phrase "abstraction and generalization".

In this approach, interestingly, I find Vygotsky to be quite methodologically in line with Ilyenkov's dialectical concepts of the abstract and the concrete, and the material and the ideal. Many core ideas of cultural-historical activity theory pass through this matrix, and Ch 6 is yet another area where I find Vygotsky leading the way. (I am still mulling over Davydov's critiques of Vygotsky's theory of concept formation - another good discussion item some day).

Ch 5 does not have any such systematic description of these relationships, however. Vygotsky certainly makes many brilliant **observations** about abstraction and generalization, and he is certainly **intuitively** searching for something like this, but he does not explicate anything about these relationships systematically, nor in a way that shows how these structures **develop** into one another - or even how the different phases within a stage change.

Ch 5, according to this way of looking at it, is more of a schematic catalog of structural stages and phases - with dialectical observations about them - than a systematic description of how concept formations dialectically change, which is the central task of Ch 6 sect 6. That is the fundamental difference between the two writings of ~1930 and ~1934, I am growing to think.

In fact, as we all know, in Ch 6, Vygotsky becomes sharply critical of how the block experiments limited him and his colleagues to creating only a **structural**, schematic view of the various structures of generalization. This outlook created, or was based, on a wrong assumption, he explains - that the child started their concepts all over again when they arrived at a new structural level. He emphasizes that just the opposite is the case.

This is one of the hidden puzzles from Ch 5 that the relations of generality concept in Ch 6 solves - it shows how specific changes in the relations of generality can produce major leaps from one general concept system to another.

I've been in some denial about **how** critical Vygotsky was in Ch 6 about the work described in Ch 5. It was interesting to look over his criticisms again in this new light. I was not correct the other day about Vygotsky only "adding" to Ch 5 in Ch 6. It is a more fundamental change than that. Vygotsky does maintain the essential structures of Ch 5, and their genetic order - he explains that. And that really was a major accomplishment of the block experiment work. But this is also the **only** positive thing Vygotsky has to say about it! Otherwise, he is quite critical.

Now, maybe some of that stuff in Ch 6 about "we should be criticized" about the block experiment work was a nod to the forced self- criticisms so common in those days of intense repression. And there do appear to be some curious voids in Ch 6 in his discussions of complexes, as David brings up. These are puzzling me.

For example, in Ch 6, Vygotsky does not provide a satisfactory distinction between complexes and preconcepts, nor does he satisfactorily visit the concept of the complex in the new light of his theory of the relations of generality. And of course, he omits mentioning pseudoconcepts at all, as David stresses. Given all the insights into complexes and pseudoconcepts in Ch 5 - for example, the role of complexive thinking in pre-history, in language change, in children's learning, in daily adult functioning - what new things can we now understand about complexive thinking in the light of the new theory? What needs to be revised? What new questions can we ask?

This makes me very curious about David's discussion about political pressures at the time to leave complexes at the front school door, as he puts it, and what role all that may have had on Vygotsky's theorizing in Ch 6.

- Steve




On Mar 25, 2010, at 4:19 PM, Martin Packer wrote:

Steve, David, Andy...

You guys are so keen to get into chapter 6, while I am intent on a good microanalysis of LSV's thinking chapter 5 that will, hopefully, prepare me for the leap to 6!

I have been looking at the video that Paula shared with us last year, and reading her microanalysis of this case of an 8-year-old child who achieved a solution to the problem. And thinking about the way that data like this make it very easy to combine the two different explanations that LSV proposed for the move from complexes (pseudoconcepts) to concepts.

To recall, I wrote that:
2. LSV seems to offer not one but two explanations of how the child (or rather the adolescent) forms concepts. The first explanation is that concepts arise from the advanced application of the processes of generalization and abstraction, specifically that the word is now used functionally for voluntary control of attention, permitting a mastery of these processes. The second explanation is based on the phenotypical identity and functional similarity of concepts and pseudoconcepts. The latter are actually complexes, but they look like concepts and so when child and adult interact the adult takes them to be concepts. The child is in a sense then using concepts without knowing it, and LSV appeals to the familiar Hegelian process of in-itself, for-others, for-self, to explain how this "internal contradiction"is the "basic genetic prerequisite" for the rise of true concepts.

I'm not suggesting that these two explanations are incompatible or mutually exclusive. But LSV does not seem to try to bring them together.

What strikes me about this child's activity is the way the explanation to an adult (Paula) gives the child the opportunity to notice how during his original organizing of the blocks his criterion shifted (from size to color to shape...). The explanation is necessary because, well, because the experimenter asks for it, but also because her concept of what the nonsense words mean differs from his complexive use. So here we see the role of the concept-for- others. As he explains, the product that his process of organizing gave rise to is laid out in front of him. As he explains, he articulates verbally the understanding of the task that he had previously enacted in practice. His explanation uses new words to direct the adult's attention, and so it directs his own. The result, Paula tells us, is that he announces that he has changed his mind, and has decided that it is size that is really important. Then he sorts the blocks again, and thought he gets tied up by the fact that "size" can mean "height" or "width," he is a step closer to the solution.

So here we see the way the difference between the adult's understanding and the child's requires the child to grasp things in a new way, and we also see the use of words to direct attention and so alter the processes of abstraction and generalization. The two explanations are at work together. Of course, to see this we need to give up any proposal that the blocks task shows us how a child develops concepts free from adult interference, but David has already pointed out how difficult it is to take this proposal at face value.

Martin


On Mar 25, 2010, at 4:30 PM, David Kellogg wrote:

Mike: Yes, the paper that Martin circulated from Rosch has what I think is a pretty good summary of the work you refer to and it's certainly relevant.

Both Davydov and Engestrom are what I would call "activity" interpretations of Chapter Six: they tend to de-emphasize the distinctness of SEMIOSIS from PERCEPTION. Martin calls this approach trying to squeeze concepts out of percepts.

Steve: Actually, this is just the returns on a short term loan, you know, YOU were the one who first showed me that preconcepts couldn't possibly be a generic name for all of the thinking that happens before concepts, and one of the quotes you gave to show this is in that list (although not in the form you gave, because once you have tasted Thinking and Speech in the non-English translations it's hard to go back to English rotgut).

Andy has a good therapist's approach to discussion; he tends to "hold up a mirror" to the patient by reformulating and recasting his own words. Our elementary school teachers do this very well too, but they tend to focus on grammar mistakes (of which there are quite a few in my original post!) I know, it's not really from therapy or from primary education; it's his training in immanent critique.

In any case, he's got me right. You notice that LSV does not use the word "pseudoconcept" anywhere in Chapter Six, although he does talk about syncretisms and complexes a fair amount. He also places the preconcept on the border between complexes and concepts. Finally, he says the preconcept is a concept that is generalized by others but not by the self. So I think the preconcept is the pseudoconcept, even though in Chapter Five he argued that psychologically speaking the pseudoconcept is a complex.

Why the change in nomenclature? Well, first of all, LSV often picks up a word from somebody else. Knocks it around a bit. Hollows it out and stuffs it with something else. And finally renames it. For example, the word "everyday concept" is clearly related to the "spontaneous concept" of Piaget (which Vygotsky actually refers to using Piaget's name in Chapter Two) but it's also quite different, because LSV totally rejects the elaborate methodology that Piaget uses to purge the child's spontaneous concepts of adult taint in "The Child's Conception of the World".

That's why I prefer Prout's translation of "academic concept" for the nonspontaneous concept (and even "self-directed speech" for private/egocentric speech, although I admit that Vygotsky never actually uses this term). So I think that arithmetic numbers are the preacademic form of this concept, but they are only one possible instantiation of the true, academic form, which is entirely relational and algebraic, which is why it forms the extreme North Pole (or South Pole, if you use Ana's map) of the measure of generality.

I also think that by translating the "science concept" as the academic concept we can include a range of higher concepts from ethics teaching and even aesthetics. Right now one of my students is using Vygotsky/Piaget's sentence completion method for testing pairs of everyday/academic concepts like "gift"/"loan", "road"/"avenue", and even 'so"/"because" and "but"/"although".

But secondly Vygotsky is trimming. All educators have been ordered to "leave complexes at the school door". In 1931 he is still reeling from the declaration of the Bolshevik Party Central Committee on pedology; he has to abandon everything he's written about complexes in education because it is now considered that they do not belong in primary education at all. But he KNOWS that primary school children think in complexes, and not concepts.

Mary had a little lamb
Whose fleece was white as snow
And everywhere that Mary went
The lamb was sure to go

So in 1934 he changes his tactics. By rechristening the pseudoconcept as the "preconcept", by chanting the slogan of leaving the complex at the school door, and above all by introducing the concept of the zone of proximal development as part of a feigned critique of pedology, he is able to make sure that complexes are "left at the school door" in name only.

It followed her to school one day.
Which was against the rules
It made the children laugh and play
To see a lamb at school...

David Kellogg
Seoul National University of Education

--- On Thu, 3/25/10, mike cole <lchcmike@gmail.com> wrote:


From: mike cole <lchcmike@gmail.com>
Subject: Re: [xmca] The strange situation
To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
Date: Thursday, March 25, 2010, 8:49 AM


I will not err by entering into this discussion until I am sure I am not
being irrelevant. Two brief comments that I think are probably not
irrelevant.

1. A lot of work has been done along lines initiated by eleanor r in the 1970's. I will check for an update of the current thinking along lines she
started and see what I can find.

2. It may be worth people's while to remember that Davydov had his own criticism of Vygotsky's notion of scientific concept which clearly does go back to Hegel. For a summary of the discussion, see Engestrom, Ch. 4 at

http://lchc.ucsd.edu/mca/Paper/Engestrom/expanding/ch4.htm

mike

On Thu, Mar 25, 2010 at 8:08 AM, Steve Gabosch <stevegabosch@me.com> wrote:

Thank you VERY much for this, David. You have just completely re- oriented me to Ch6sect6 - I feel like I woke up and turned a light on and discovered
I had only been getting 1/3 of it, and now I am getting 2/3 of that
difficult and fascinating section. This was extremely helpful. I am finding that the more I set aside what I thought I knew about concept
formation from Ch5, the more I understand Ch6.

What is your take on the relationship between the pseudoconcept of Ch5 and
the preconcept of Ch6?

- Steve





On Mar 24, 2010, at 10:02 PM, David Kellogg wrote:

 Andy, Steve:

Take a look at these. The translations are my own but the page numbers
suggest the corresponding bits in your Minick translation.

“We have first of all succeeded in discovering that generality
(differences in generality) does not coincide with the structure of
generalization and its different stages such as we found them in our
experimental study on the formation of concepts: syncretic images,
complexes, preconcepts, and concepts. (roughly, p. 225 in your Minick)”

You can see from this that "preconcepts" is NOT a general term including syncretisms, complexes any more than "rose" is a general term including
daisies and daffodils.

“In the first place, concepts of different generality are possible in a same generalization structure. For example, in the structure of concepts by complexes it is possible for concepts of different levels of generality to exist: flower, and rose. In truth, we must state a reservation from the very outset, that is to say that the relationship of generalization ”flower-rose”
will be different in each structure of generalization, for example,
different in the structure of complexes from in the structure of
preconcepts.” (225)

We can see from this that LSV does NOT consider a preconcept to be a
complex.

“Thanks to the analysis of the real concepts of the child, we have been able to study some less well-known properties of syncretic formations, complexes, and preconcepts and to establish what in each of these spheres of thinking is shown to be different in the relationship with the object as well as the apprehension of the object by thought, that is to say, how the two fundamental elements which characterize concepts are revealed to be
different from one stage to another.” (228)

Once again, "preconcepts" are not the preconceptual functional equivalents of concepts (that is, they are not a hypernym for syncretic heaps and complexes). But here Vygotsky suggests that there are two processes and not
one at work in concept formation.

One is indeed a form of activity: it's a relationship with the object, e.g. ostension, indication, and naming. But the other is "the apprehension of the object by thought", the way in which the object is represented
(reflected/refracted/semiotically reproduced) by the mind.

“What we have managed to establish here with respect to the passage from the preconcepts of the schoolchild to the concepts of the adolescent is the same thing that we managed to establish in the preceding study with respect to the passage of generalized perceptions to general representations, that
is to say syncretic formations and complexes.” (230)

This appears to be a direct reference to Chapter Five. In 1931, LSV
considered this to be a study of concept formation in ADOLESCENTS. But now he appears to have changed his mind: the previous chapter is concerned with the passage from generalized perceptions to general representations, and is thus a matter of preschoolers. This is quite consistent with what Paula did
with three year olds to eight year olds.

“Just as in that case it turned out that a new stage in the development of
generalizations can only be attained by the transformation, not the
annulment, of the preceding stage, by the generalization of the objects already generalized, not by proceeding anew from the generalization of single objects, in the same way here the study has shown that the transition from preconcepts (of which the typical example is the arithmetical concept of the school child) to the true concepts of the adolescent (of which the typical example is the algebraic concept) happens through the generalization
of objects which have already been generalized.”

And here we see why! The generalized perception is the PRECONDITION of the general representation. And the general representation is the precondition
of the concept. The example he gives us is numbers.

Of course, at the very lowest level, numbers really are the result of the activity of the perceptible and perceptual activity of counting. But take away the objects, and the number remains as a generalized representation. And when we take away the number, and deal only with the realtion of number,
the concept remains.

"The preconcept is the abstraction of the number, detached from the object and, founded on this abstraction, the generalization of the numerical properties of the object. The concept is the abstraction detached from the number and, founded on it, the generalization of any relation between
numbers. But the abstraction and generalization of ideas differs
fundamentally from the abstraction and the generalization of things. It is not a pursuit of movement in the same direction or its culmination, it is the beginning of a movement in a new direction, a transition to a new and
higher plane of thinking. (230)"

This of course returns us to a point that Vygotsky made in the very first chapter and returns again to in the very last: the "dialectical leap" is not
simply from inanimate to animate, but from perception to thinking.

There is a qualitative difference between the abstraction and
generalization of perceptions and the abstraction and generalization of thoughts; they are distinct processes, and the word "activity" applies much
more accurately to the former than the latter.

David Kellogg
Seoul National University of Education




--- On Wed, 3/24/10, Andy Blunden <ablunden@mira.net> wrote:


From: Andy Blunden <ablunden@mira.net>
Subject: Re: [xmca] The strange situation
To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
Date: Wednesday, March 24, 2010, 9:30 PM


Steve, briefly and without references, my take was:

* *preconcepts* are a family name for all the thought-forms prior to true concepts and so includes potential concepts, pseduoconcepts, complexes. etc.

* *potential concepts* are, as far as I can, see the highest type of pseudoconcept, marked by its "transferability" to different sensory fields. Here the attributes have been completely isolated from their substratum.

* *complex* is a family name for a whole group of forms including both
pseudo- and potential concepts.

Andy

Steve Gabosch wrote:

David, thanks again for these extremely useful files of your translations of T&S from Meccaci, Seve, Prout, and your Korean team. I am in awe of the
work you did, and are still doing.

I thought where we got stuck last year was on that pesky creature from Ch 5, the 'potential concept,' not the clearer concept, 'pseudoconcept'. I think Vygotsky leaves no doubt that the pseudoconcept is a complex. I am
still struggling with precisely what a potential concept is.

Both complicated concepts, potential concept and pseudoconcept, seem to be subsumed into the Ch 6 term 'preconcept'. That move gives us a simpler term, but leaves many questions unanswered. It leaves us little choice but
to investigate concept formation ourselves.

Martin, I would be most interested, when you have the time, if you took your recent very excellent questions and reframed them, or more precisely, sharpened them, in light of Ch 6. I think some important work can be done analyzing Ch 5 in terms of Ch 6 - and looking at Ch 6, especially section 6,
in terms of Ch 5.

Apparently about 3, 4 or 5 years did separate the main writing of these two chapters, as you and Paula suggest. On one hand, there is an explosion of ideas in Ch 6 sect 6 that are barely touched on or anticipated in Ch 5. On the other hand, the rich, specific ideas in Ch 5 are insufficiently dealt in light of the new, general ideas in Ch 6 sect 6. Vygotsky left that
challenge to us as well.

- Steve





On Mar 24, 2010, at 5:35 PM, David Kellogg wrote:

 Martin, Steve:

Last night I showed a picture of an iguana to my graduate seminar and asked what it was. Everybody said it was an ALLIGATOR. This is strange, because the word "iguana" exists as a loan word from English in Korean, and
in fact everybody confirmed that they knew the word, but the word
"alligator" does not exist in Korean and instead we use a Chinese loan word
(literally, "evil fish").

What this means is that my grads have the WORD but not the CONCEPT of Iguana--it is an example of a concept for others but not for myself. This is not the only situation where that is true, of course. For example, the words "Miss" and "Mister" also exist in Korean as loan words, but they are quite impolite and used to refer to social inferiors (bar girls, prostitutes, secretaries or waiters or male underlings of one kind or another). Here too the concept of the English polite form of address exists as a word but not
as a concept.

Last year I suggested to Steve that in Chapter Six Vygotsky uses the word "preconcept" to refer to this situation, and that therefore the word "preconcept" is used in preference to "pseudoconcept" in Chapter Six. Steve objected that Chapter Five clearly says that a pseudoconcept is not a concept at all, but a complex, while Chapter Six says that it is indeed a
concept, although not a concept for myself.

I'm still unconvinced. As Steve says there really IS a shift of opinion on a number of issues in Chapter Six (the carry over from one structure of generalization to another, for example, and also the issue of whether concepts can be taught to pre-adolescents). The word "pseudoconcept", which is so misleading that it even confuses LSV himself sometimes, is not LSV's coinage; he took it from the Sterns,who took it from somebody else.

So it seems to me that "pseudoconcept" in Chapter Five is a concept for others (for the Sterns), and it only becomes a concept for LSV himself in
Chapter Six!

 David Kellogg
Seoul National University of Education

Attached is OUR re-reading of Chapter Six, here in Seoul.Sorry about the
Korean!

--- On Wed, 3/24/10, Martin Packer <packer@duq.edu> wrote:


From: Martin Packer <packer@duq.edu>
Subject: Re: [xmca] The strange situation
To: "eXtended Mind, Culture, Activity" <xmca@weber.ucsd.edu>
Date: Wednesday, March 24, 2010, 12:57 PM


Thanks, Steve,

I've been putting off re-reading chapter 6, but I have to bite the bullet soon. I was thinking that trying to figure out what LSV had come up with and written about in chap 5 (and Paula has pointed out that he seems to have had this figured out by 1930) would itself be valuable. But you make a
cogent argument.

Martin

On Mar 24, 2010, at 1:39 PM, Steve Gabosch wrote:

 These are really, really good questions, Martin.  All worth very
serious exploration.

My take on Chapter 5, after doing some study of it, and Chapter 6, last year with David Ke. and Paula T., and some discussion here on xmca, is that Ch 5 might be best understood in terms of Chapter 6, especially section 6 starting on pg 224 of Vol 1. Here Vygotsky gets to his major theoretical discussion of systems of concepts, and critiques the limitations of the
block experiments on page 228 and 229.

He explains that the block experiment "ignored the fact that **each new stage in the development of generalization depends on the generalizations found in the preceding stages.**" pg 229. He was critical of the block experiment not revealing connections or transitions between the stages of concept development. He felt he was able to reveal these connections with
the experiments described in Chapter 6.

It is important to emphasize that he does not at all **reject** the work described in Chapter 5 - the syncretic heap, complexes, and what he now calls preconcepts (was pseudoconcepts), and true concepts, are still intact - but he **adds** a whole new level of theorizing that he saw as crucial - suggestions for solutions to "the central problem" of his research in Chapter 6, involving systems and relationships of generality, the law of concept equivalence (any concept can be represented through other concepts in an infinite number of ways), measures of generality, systems of concepts, etc. Vygotsky's most advanced thinking about concept formation is here in this section. And some of your very good questions are addressed.

This is why I think that Chapter 5 needs to be seen as something of a building block toward section 6 in Chapter 6, and that it might be easier to read Chapter 6 sect 6 first and work backwards, or work them together as one study. And don't forget that Vygotsky's publisher or maybe even Vygotsky himself got longitude and latitude backwards in the globe metaphor when he
explains the law of concept equivalence! (pg 226)  LOL

Chapter 6 as a whole, of course, has much material on everyday vs scientific concepts, as well as the oft-quoted passages on the zone of proximal development, so that difficult section 6 in Ch 6 kind of gets overshadowed, and maybe a little disconnected from Chapter 5. The two need to be dialectically joined, I believe, to really grasp what Vygotsky was trying to do in both chapters. And there is also some discussion on pg 189 in section 2 in Chapter 6, and maybe a few other places in that chapter, about complexes and so forth, that may also shed some helpful light on some
specifics in Chapter 5.

- Steve



On Mar 23, 2010, at 1:25 PM, Martin Packer wrote:

I am taking the liberty of recycling this subject heading, after
having spent some time re-reading the posts over the weekend. I seem to have played a large part in hijacking this thread some time last year, with my
obsession over the meaning of the term 'reflection.'

So this message is partly penance, but it also me trying to make sense of LSV's block task and what it tells us about his views of concepts, and
their development. I find myself with the following questions:

1. It seems to be the case that in chapter 5 LSV doesn't mention the distinction between everyday concepts and scientific concepts. Is it at all possible that what in chapter 6 he calls "everyday concepts" are what he refers to in chapter 5 as complexes? I suspect not, but the question seems
worth asking.

2. LSV seems to offer not one but two explanations of how the child (or rather the adolescent) forms concepts. The first explanation is that concepts arise from the advanced application of the processes of generalization and abstraction, specifically that the word is now used functionally for voluntary control of attention, permitting a mastery of these processes. The second explanation is based on the phenotypical identity and functional similarity of concepts and pseudoconcepts. The latter are actually complexes, but they look like concepts and so when child and adult interact the adult takes them to be concepts. The child is in a sense then using concepts without knowing it, and LSV appeals to the familiar Hegelian process of in-itself, for-others, for-self, to explain how this "internal contradiction"is the "basic genetic prerequisite" for the
rise of true concepts.

I'm not suggesting that these two explanations are incompatible or mutually exclusive. But LSV does not seem to try to bring them together.

3. In other words, this second explanation is another case of
"internalization," and the application of the general genetic law of cultural development. But LSV adds that this "peculiar genetic situation" in the move from pseudoconcepts to concepts should be considered the general rule rather than the exception in children's intellectual development. Does this not suggest that this same kind of process occurs as the child moves
from heaps to complexes?

4. Generalization and abstraction are the two "channels" in the
development of concepts - LSV refers to them also as "complexing" and "segregating." The first is very familiar by the time we get to chapter 5: he has been writing about the way a word is a generalization since the start (this is where as David has pointed out we find the quotation from Sapir.) But abstraction seems to appear out of nowhere. Is there a treatment of abstraction/segregating elsewhere in the book that I have missed?

5. LSV seems to get to the end of chapter 5 without ever telling us exactly what a concept it. He suggests that it involves hierarchy, and connections that are abstract, essential, and homogeneous. He proposes that particular and general are linked. He adds that "most important" is "the unity of form and content," for this is what makes thinking in concepts a "real revolution." Can anyone pull these somewhat diverse (complexive?) characteristics together for me? Do they harmonize with the treatment of
concepts (of both kinds) in chapter 6?

6. Finally, less a question than an observation. LSV writes at the close of chapter 5 of the way that “Concept thinking is a new form of intellectual activity, a new mode of conduct, a new intellectual mechanism. The intellect is able to find a new and unprecedented modus operandi in this particular activity and a new function becomes available within the system of intellectual functions which is distinctive both in its composition and structure as well as in the way it functions.” I take this as a clear indication that for LSV a concept is not simply a new kind of mental representation. It is, as Rosch proposes, a new way of relating to the
world.

Any guidance through this thicket will be gratefully accepted!

Martin

_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca


_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca


_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca



<Chapter six all.doc>_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca


_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca


--
------------------------------------------------------------------------
Andy Blunden http://www.erythrospress.com/
Classics in Activity Theory: Hegel, Leontyev, Meshcheryakov, Ilyenkov $20
ea

_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca




_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca


_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca

_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca




_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca

_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca

_______________________________________________
xmca mailing list
xmca@weber.ucsd.edu
http://dss.ucsd.edu/mailman/listinfo/xmca